Paolo Virno
Déjà Vu and the End of History
Watching Themselves Live1
When psychiatrists refer to déjà vu, they do not mean a
known event of the past playing out again, accompanied by either euphoric
amazement or bored condescension. Rather, here we have an only apparent
repetition, one that is entirely illusory. We believe that we have already
experienced (or seen, heard, done, etc.) something that is, in fact, happening
for the first time at this very moment. We mistake the current experience for
the very faithful copy of an original that never really existed. We believe that
we are recognizing something of which we are only now cognizant. As such, we
could also describe déjà vu in terms of “false recognition.”
Déjà vu does not entail a defect of memory, nor its
qualitative alteration. Rather, it means the untrammelled extension of memory’s
jurisdiction, of its dominion. Rather than limit itself to preserving traces of
times past, memory also applies itself to actuality, to the evanescent “now.”
The instantaneous present takes the form of memory, and is re-evoked even as it
is taking place. But what can “remembering the present” mean, except having the
irresistible sensation of having already experienced it previously? Inasmuch as
it is an object of memory, the “now” is camouflaged as the already-been, and is
thus duplicated in an imaginary “back then,” in a fictitious “other-then.” It
goes without saying that between the current event, considered a mere repeat,
and the phantom original prototype, there is no mere analogy, but rather the
most complete identity. The present and the pseudo-past, which have the same
perceptual and emotional content, are indistinguishable. The consequence is a
troubling one: every act and every word that I say and do
now seems
destined to repeat, step by step, the course that was fixed back then, without
the possibility of omitting or changing anything. As Henri Bergson put it in
“Le souvenir du Présent et la Fausse Reconnaissance”: “
We feel that we
choose and will, but that we are choosing what is imposed on us and
willing the inevitable.”
2
The state of mind correlated to déjà vu is that typical of
those set on watching themselves live. This means apathy, fatalism,
and indifference to a future that seems prescribed even down to the last
detail. Since the present is dressed in the clothes of an irrevocable past,
these people must renounce any influence on how the present plays out. It is
impossible to change something that has taken on the appearances of memory. As
such, they give up on action. Or, better, they becomespectators of
their own actions, almost as if these were part of an already-known and
unalterable script. They are dumbfounded spectators, sometimes ironic and often
inclined to cynicism. The individual at the mercy of the déjà vu is her own
epigone. To her eyes, the historical scansion of events is suspended or
paralyzed; the distinction between before and after, cause and effect, seems
futile and even derisory.
The phenomenon of “false recognition” allows us to decipher
critically the fundamental idea of every philosophy of history: the end, the
exhaustion, or the implosion of history itself. Above all, it allows us to
settle accounts with the contemporary—that is, “postmodern”—version of this
idea, which descends from a noble lineage and complicated family tree.
According to Baudrillard and his miniature disciples, history thins out to the
point of vanishing when the millenarian aspiration to wipe out the duration of
time (and, with this, any irritating delays) appears to have been satisfied by
the instantaneousness of information, real-time communications, and by the
desire to lay “hold of things almost before they have taken place.”
3 And
yet the affirmation of an eternal present, a centripetal and despotic
actuality,
is provoked by déjà vu, namely by the form of experience in which there prevails—as
Bergson put it—“the feeling that
the future is closed, that the
situation is detached from everything although I am attached to it.”
4 In
capricious, rampant years of history, Karl Mannheim prophesied:
It is possible … that in the future, in a world in which
there is never anything new, in which all is finished and each moment a
repetition of the past, there can exist a condition in which thought is utterly
devoid of all ideological and utopian elements.
5
A posthistorical situation, then; but also, at the same
time, a condition marked by the mnestic pathology of which we have already
spoken: “there is never anything new … each moment [is] a repetition of the
past.”
Now, however, we need to interrupt this game of assonances
and analogies. To understand the increasing fragility of historical experience
and, at the same time, to refute the mediocre ideologies that set up camp on
this terrain, it is necessary to observe more closely the actual texture of
“false recognition.” What clay is a memory of the present made
of? How is it formed? What does it reveal?
The Temporality of the Possible
It is in the past that we find the center of gravity of the
temporality of potential. This is still something of an enigma, however. In
order to illustrate its meaning and significance, it is worth asking ourselves,
first of all, what past it concerns, and how the perennial “having been” of the
virtual is articulated. This is nothing more than a morphological description,
on the basis of which we can then address the important question: To what
experience or way of being does such a “back then” correspond?
The past in which the possible is inscribed is neither
recent nor remote: in “Le possible et le réel,” Bergson speaks of a “
passé
indéfini,” of an incalculable “
de tout temps,” a formless
other-then.
6 And
in “Le souvenir du present,” we read that in false recognition, the memory is
never located at a specific point in the past, but rather in “the
past
in general.” What is at issue here is not this or that former present, with
its own unique countenance, but rather a simple “before” that cannot be
circumscribed within any chronological order: “a past that has no date and can
have none.”
7 The
past-in-general accompanies every actuality like an aura—without, though,
itself having ever been actual. It is, therefore, the pure
form of
anteriority that is here at work. It is an
a priori form, with
the capacity to subordinate any experience whatsoever to itself: not just that
which has already been, but also current experience and what is now to come. We
ought to recognize that “a representation can bear the mark of the past
independently of what it represents.”
8
If representation concerns a particular (dateable, defined)
past, the past-form so closely adheres to its object that it goes almost
unperceived. Conversely, where the “now” is depicted as the “back then”
(namely, where we have a memory of the present) the past-in-general sticks out
in sharp relief. The déjà vu is its epiphany. Moreover, the past-form also
corresponds to the representation of the future. How? Whenever we adopt the
future perfect tense of a verb, the future seems to be emptied out, locked
away: “I will have enjoyed,” “I will have had many opportunities,” and so on.
In all such cases, what does not yet exist is put behind us, and we include it
in the past-in-general, making it a matter of memory. The future perfect is the
memory
of what is to come.
9
Whatever the temporal location of the experience to which we
are referring, the past-form always implies that the actual must step back in
favor of the potential. An event that took place many years ago is “past” in a
double sense: something that was perceived and something that was remembered as
it took place, a real “back then” and a virtual “back then,” the
chronologically situated past and the past-in-general. An event in the present,
as we know, demonstrates its own enduring potential as soon as its image is
anachronistically projected back onto the “passé indéfini.” An event
that takes place subsequently, will have been possible: contingency
is inherent within future states of affairs (or rather, seems to be one of
their salient traits) precisely and only because they also have a place in the
past-in-general, have something of the previous about them,
and are vested with memory.
In a well-known passage of his Confessions,
Augustine writes:
But even now it is manifest and clear that there are neither
times future nor times past. Thus it is not properly said that there are three
times, past, present, and future. Perhaps it might be said rightly that there
are three times: a time present of things past; a time present of things
present; and a time present of things future. For these three do coexist somehow
in the soul, for otherwise I could not see them. The time present of things
past is memory; the time present of things present is direct experience; the
time present of things future is expectation.
10
And yet such a scansion, with its axis in the current
present (the object of perception or “direct intuition”), speaks to the
modality of the real, rather than to the modality of the possible. The past—or
better, the indeterminate “de tout temps”—is preeminent with regard to
the potentially existing. Paraphrasing Augustine, we ought speak of a past
of the past (the old “memory of the present” now placed side-by-side
with the perception of the present); of a past of the present (as
arises in the déjà vu phenomenon); and a past of the future (the
memory of what is to come, as established by what “will have been”).
Language as the Indefinite Past
The past that was never actual, a “before” with no date, the
pure form of the previous: such are the structural characteristics of the time
pertaining to possibility. But such a morphological description is only one
first step. The past-form is not, indeed, a mental abstraction (possible to
grasp by identifying what the countless particular pasts have in common), nor a
mere psychological device. Nothing is less “formalistic” than this form: it
does not limit itself to making its mark on many and varied representations,
but also exhibits its own particular mode of existence. The
past-in-general, beyond being a “how?,” is also and above all a “what?”: it
refers to an aspect of existence, and is incarnated in an unavoidable concrete
process. Our next task, then, consists in understanding what the
past-in-general is, or—the same thing—in naming the potential nestled within
it.
The past-in-general is, in the first place, language.
Meaning: the phonetic, lexical, and grammatical system, which exists in the
sense of an inexhaustible potential, a potential that is perennial because it
is never exhausted or attenuated by the ensemble of its realizations. But the
term “language” here has a more extensive—or less rigorous—meaning than
Saussure gives it: it also indicates the general disposition towards
articulated discourse, the very fact that we can speak. Here we are referring
to the language faculty as such, not only the system of signs (langue in
the strict sense, that is) that allows and mediates its exercise.
According to psychiatrists, people subject to déjà vu are,
without exception, inclined to find familiar words strange. Their vocabulary is
immobilized, stopping the phrase in its tracks: derailed from its habitual use,
it comes into sharp relief, and produces a sort of echo. We are suddenly struck
by certain among its material characteristics (the excess of vowels in “queue,”
for example), or by the obviousness of its etymology, or by a previously
unnoticed homonymy. The familiar word is split in two: we use it to say
something, but, at the same time, we put it in inverted commas, as if it were a
quotation. It is used but also mentioned;
perceived in its actuality, and together with this remembered as something
virtual. On the one hand, the mention of the term—simultaneous to its
use—situates what is being said in the past. On the other hand, its mention
re-evokes the fact that it belongs to the infinite potential of language,
restoring the dictum to the terms of the speakable, and
referring the act of speaking back to the faculty that made it possible. On the
one hand and the other: But is it really the case that two distinct aspects are
at play here? Or are we talking about one and the same thing? On closer
inspection, the mention of the familiar word pushes it back into the passé
indéfini precisely insofar as it reassimilates it to language. And
language is, in itself, the purely previous, an indeterminate other-then. The
language faculty is the never-present “back then” to which what I now utter can
always look back.
The Snobbery of Memory
This reflection on the two different forms of anachronism
now allows us to formulate a detailed and sharp-pointed thesis that will not be
blunted by too many nuances. More than a thesis, it is a guide-to-thought with
which we can mount an offensive against certain theories and emotional
inclinations that postulate the completion or collapse of the process of
history.
The feeling of déjà vu, awakened by “false recognition,”
leads us to believe that even if we are faced with continuous change,
everything is the same, everything is repeating itself. It goes without saying,
however, that there would be no “false recognition” if it were not for “the
memory of the present.” Only where the virtual is in full flower right next to
the actual could we ever illusorily confuse it for something that we have
experienced already. The real anachronism makes use of materials that the
formal anachronism puts at its disposal: and nothing else beyond them. As such,
it uses its opposite as its own lever. But since “false recognition” conceals
the genesis of historical time, the genesis that the “memory of the present,”
conversely, reveals and displays, to state that the former presupposes the
latter has a consequence of some significance (here accorded the value of a
“thesis”). Namely: the “end of history” is an idea, or state of mind,
that arises precisely when the very condition of possibility of history comes
into view; when the root of all historical activity is cast out onto the
surface of historical becoming, and is evident as a phenomenon; when thehistoricity of
experience is itself also manifested historically.
The best way to examine this guide-to-thought more closely
is to put it to the test. That is, we ought to test the waters of its
explanatory capacity and critical force in relation to an example text. In a
long footnote to his
Introduction à la lecture de Hegel, Alexandre
Kojève maintains that the exhaustion of history diagnosed by Hegel is no
longer, in our epoch, some future eventuality, but rather is a
fait
accompli.11 The
industrial societies of the post-Second World War period, in this view, had now
left behind the struggle against nature and the struggle for mutual
recognition. Labor—that is, the opposition between Subject and Object—was
losing weight and significance as automated production processes captured and subjugated
nature in such measure as to allow for a stable relation with it. Similarly,
politics—the search for the recognition of others by way of wars and
revolutions—was also declining. The bloody conflicts of the last century
represented only a “spatial extension” of the essential results achieved once
and for all time by Robespierre and Napoleon. Also disappearing together with
Labor and Politics is “Action in the strong sense of the term,” which,
rejecting “the given,” was always seeking to establish a historically new
world. But what forms of life prevail in post-historical societies? Kojève saw
two of them, a pair that diverged and were even opposites.
On the one hand, the post-history in which we are supposedly
immersed is explained as man “becoming an animal again.” Rather than inhabiting
a world with struggle and labor, the living being of the Homo sapiens species
is now encapsulated in an environment, to which it adapts without
any kind of friction. Certainly, even after the conclusion of the business of
History, we will build houses and create works of art, but following the same
impulse that leads a bird to make its nest or a spider to spin its web. Nothing
like happiness is any longer in question: rather, “men will surely be content as
a result of their artistic,erotic, and playful behavior
inasmuch as, by definition, they will be contented with it.” Also accounted for
here is the “definitive disappearance of human discourse (Logos) in the
strict sense.” In its place, “vocal signals or sign ‘language’” will
proliferate, to which we would react by conditioned reflex: nothing much
different from “what is supposed to be the ‘language’ of bees.” In Kojève’s
view, the American way of life, in which the eternal present
typical of an “environment” dominates, exemplifies well the condition of
post-historical animals.
Another way of being also comes into view at the end of
history, diametrically opposed to the one just sketched out. It is a matter of snobbery.
That is to say, an affected attitude that shrinks from any utilitarian
automatism and clashes with the “‘animal’ or ‘natural’ given.” Though having
nothing to do with Labor or “warlike and revolutionary Fights,” the snob
nonetheless maintains a separation between the forms and contents of
his own activity, such as to guarantee the former a marked independence from
(and supremacy over) the latter. The unequalled model of this way of being is
Japanese culture: there, indeed, Noh theatre, the tea ceremony, and the art of
flower arranging have built up a widespread propensity to “live according to
totally formalized values.” No longer historical yet still human (the fracture
between Subject and Object having been reinvented), Japanese snobbery,
according to Kojève, alludes to a principle-hope of general applicability:
While henceforth speaking in an adequate fashion
of everything that is given to him, post-historical Man must continue to detach “form”
from “content,” doing so no longer in order actively to transform the latter,
but so that he may oppose himself as a pure “form” to himself
and to others taken as “content” of any sort.
Becoming an animal again, or else snobbery. The alternative
proposed by Kojève is in many aspects akin to that with which we dealt in
earlier: real anachronism or formal anachronism, false recognition or memory of
the present. However, in order to make clear this consonance, we must call into
question the conceptual schema within which Kojève inscribes his pair of
opposed choices. And it attracts two principal objections.
First off, far from it playing a protagonist’s role on the
little stage of post-history, we could even say that snobbery constitutes the
very quintessence of historical life. Its prerogative is to show the autonomy
and exuberance of “forms” with respect to “contents”: But what are this
autonomy and exuberance, other than the prerequisite of Labor
and Politics: in other words, “Action in the strong sense of the term”?
Snobbery unveils the foundation of historical conflicts, since it devotes
itself to representing, through a series of determinate acts, the contrast that
generally exists between human action and “the given.” Detaching “forms” from
“contents,” snobbery factually expresses the impossibility of
any fact entirely realizing the corresponding capacity-to-do.
To put it another way: snobbery is a peculiar praxis that reflects in
itself—and relentlessly exhibits—the historicity of every type of praxis
(including “snobbish” praxis as well, of course). To attribute a
post-historical character to the snob is a classic case of being blinded by too
much light.
Secondly, “becoming an animal again” is not a biological
fate, corresponding to the disappearance of any friction with nature. On the
contrary, it is an existential possibility that reveals itself insofar as the
gap with “the given” is exaggeratedly accentuated, becomes most visible, and is
experienced as such. But this accentuation, as well as the
visibility and direct experience of the gap with “the given,” is the result of
snobbery. As such, we must say that “becoming an animal again” is the
existential possibility that reveals itself on the basis of the full
affirmation of the snobbish lifestyle. For Kojève, the post-historical animal
always adheres symbiotically to the “contents” of its action, while the snob
distances himself from them, counterpoising to this the autonomy of “forms.”
But he is mistaken here. Such a symbiotic adherence would only be conceivable,
in truth, if we supposed thatHomo sapiens somersaulted into the
immutable condition of the wolf or the ape; but if we did suppose such a
somersault, the self-distancing subsequently operated by the snob would itself
be inconceivable. On closer inspection, the fracture between the “forms” and
“contents” of activity is at the basis of both modes of being.
The division that separates and renders them antithetical is, rather, the
following: the snob tries to live at the level of this fracture, understanding
that the source of history is to be found within it; the post-historical
animal, conversely, makes the overpopulation of forms into an environment at
one remove, viscous and all-embracing, and adapts to its
prescriptions in virtue of some (pseudo-)instinctive behavior. To use Kojève’s
example: the post-historical animal is he who reduces the most elaborate,
affected aspects of the tea ceremony to an immediate “given.” Precisely because
they are detached from their natural “contents,” and precisely because of their
independence (and hypertrophy), “forms” are surreptitiously taken for a catalog
of minute “contents”—and with this, their frictionless mutual penetration does
indeed seem possible.
The post-historical animal and the snob do not limit
themselves to coexisting spatially, each of them extraneous and refractory with
regard to the other. Within the latter we can still make out the silhouette of
the former, even if it has been disfigured and upended. The intimate
relationship between these two contenders does not, however, blunt the contest
itself. The antithesis between these two forms of life is all the more radical,
indeed, the more they are based on identical premises and defined against the
same background. This background is not, as Kojève supposes, the “end of
history.” On the contrary, the opposition between “becoming an animal again”
and snobbery is resolved on the stage of a hyper-historical epoch:
the epoch in which, let us repeat, not only do we experience historical events,
but we face up to the very thing that confers a historical tone on every event.
False recognition suits “becoming an animal again” very
well. And the converse is also true: “becoming an animal again” announces
itself first and foremost as false recognition. When today’s potential is
confused for an already-experienced act, which we are now constrained to copy
unvaryingly, human praxis degenerates into repetitive, predetermined behavior
patterns. To identify the faculty (capacity-to-do) with a list of specific
performances (faits accomplis) carves out an environment for us within
which any freedom from “the given” is imperceptible. It is clear, however, that
this confusion and this identification would be impossible if the potential and
the faculty had not acquired an autonomous significance thanks to the snobbish
memory of the present. When we experience language through the prism of each
concrete utterance, communication resembles a weft of “vocal signals or sign
‘language,’” but, in experiencing it, we take it for an immense reservoir of already-spoken
words, to be repeated and repeated again in correspondence with environmental
stimuli. The impulse for happiness declines, and people are simply content
(inasmuch as they are contented with their own behavior), when
the disposition to enjoy pleasure appears as such—as distinct from a single
actual pleasure—but, at the same time, it is equated (through “false
recognition,” indeed) with the sum of already-enjoyed pleasures.
The Modernariat
The excess of memory, which without doubt characterizes the
contemporary situation, has a name: the memory of the present. This
latter, rather than remaining a fundamental and yet hidden characteristic of
the mnestic faculty, breaks through to the surface and is explicitly manifest.
What is excessive is not per se the split in every instant between a perceived
“now” and a remembered “now,” but rather the fact that this split has become
fully visible. To what do we owe such a radical disclosure? Perhaps to a
pathological “lack of attention to life,” as Bergson claims? Nothing of the
kind. The memory of the present, whose peculiar function is precisely to
represent the possible, presents itself unreservedly when the experience of the
possible assumes a crucial importance in the fulfillment of life’s tasks. It is
the objective preeminence of the virtual in any given type of praxis that
brings the mnestic mechanism openly into relief—in determining the temporality
of the virtual, this mechanism opens the way to the virtual itself. The excess
of memory does not induce lethargy and resignation, but on the
contrary guarantees the most intense alacrity.
The paralysis of action, often accompanied by an ironic
disillusionment, derives above all from the inability to bear the experience of
the possible. To put it another way, the effective cause of this paralysis is
the overturning of the memory of the present in false recognition,
which, as we know, reconfigures today’s possible as a previously-existing real
that we must now inevitably reiterate. Since the memory of the present is an
explicit, pervasive phenomenon, even its direct negation—that is, false
recognition—is immediately in evidence. Déjà vu is, indeed, a pathology: but,
we must add, it is a public pathology.
In the contemporary situation, apparently in harmony with
the plot of the second of Nietzsche’s Untimely Meditations, the overabundance
of memory entails an overabundance of history. This does not, however, mean the
maniacal (and asphyxiating) predominance of historiographical studies. The
problem is something rather more extreme: the unprecedented proximity of every
particular instance of action and suffering to history’s conditions of
possibility, namely what historicizes action and suffering per
se.
In our epoch, the root of acting historically (the
coexistence of, as well as the discrepancy between, potential and act) has acquired
empirical and even pragmatic significance as a phenomenon. There is no work
task today that does not require—if it is to be discharged in full—the
exhibition of the generic psycho-physical disposition to produce (namely,
labor-power), which goes beyond the task itself. Nor is there any effective,
pertinent discourse today that, beyond communicating something, does not also
have to demonstrate the speaker’s linguistic competence pure and simple, namely
the capacity-to-speak (language), which always exceeds the content that the
communication happens to have. The formal anachronism thus also itself becomes
a public mechanism, an inevitable requisite of production and
discourse. The overabundance of history (connected to the overabundance of
memory) points us to where human praxis is directly grappling with the
difference between faculty and performance, which constitutes history’s
condition of possibility.
Nietzsche held that “at the point of a certain excess of
history, life crumbles and degenerates—as does, ultimately, as a result of this
degeneration, history itself, as well.” We can here put our own name to this
statement, on condition that the original meaning is altered. The idea of an
“end of history” is not the consequence of excess, as
Nietzsche hypothesizes, but rather the consequence of its obfuscation. It is
also true, moreover, that this obfuscation presupposes a revelation: it
concerns something (namely, the overabundance of history) on which our gaze is
now fixed. Let us consider these two aspects more closely. The post-historical
state of mind is awakened by the overturning of the (historicizing) formal
anachronism in the real anachronism, which is symmetrically opposed
to it. The real anachronism conceals the difference between potential and act
(the foundation of historicity), thus reducing potential to a previous act, a
faculty to past performances, and language to already-spoken words.
Nonetheless, the radical difference between capacity-to-do and faits
accomplis is subject to a transfiguration—one that conceals this
difference—precisely and only when it comes to the fore, when it is empirically
most dazzling. The real anachronism is based on the formal anachronism,
attesting to its opposite as it clashes with and deforms it. The impression
that the historical process is stuck (“history itself … crumbles and
degenerates”) does indeed arise when human praxis stands closest to history’s
condition of possibility (“a certain excess of history”), but it arises as a
reaction that detracts from it, or what Dante called acontrapasso.
Here, we get to something else that perhaps ought to be
counted among the many ways in which we can formulate the salient problem of
the contemporary situation. Namely, learning to experience the memory of the
present (or better, its explicit, pervasive character) as such, thus liberating
it from the nemesis that degrades it into false recognition. Learning to
experience the memory of the present means to attain the possibility of a
fully
historical existence. Such a possibility, if it is not incarnated in a set
of habits—that is, in an ethos—will not remain neglected, ever-flickering on
the horizon, but rather penetrates into its opposite, taking on the semblance
of the “end of history.” And that is what is happening today, in the main.
Faced with the hyper-historicity of experience, postmodern ideology hurries to
play the broken record of the déjà vu, simultaneously both sweet and gloomy.
Everything has already been; history has fallen “into the order of the
recyclable”; we are destined, for better or for worse, to “the massive recall,
at every moment, of all the patterns of our life”
12;
every action has the status and the mannerisms of a quotation.
Making its mark on the contemporary public spirit, the déjà
vu (or false recognition, or real anachronism) determines collective behaviors,
lifestyles, and emotional propensities. To illustrate these behaviors,
lifestyles, and propensities in a synthetic (yet not elusive) manner, it is
opportune again to turn to the second of Nietzsche’s Untimely
Meditations. We know already that the déjà vu subjects us to a pseudo-past,
the fictitious “back then” that the present seems compelled zealously to
reproduce. But every relationship with the past, even when it is utterly
illusory, requires the development of a certain historiographical talent.
Obviously what is in question here is not a scientific methodology, but an
undertone of common sense, the nonpremeditated inclination to take care of what
has been. The question that makes us again turn to Nietzsche’s text is more or
less the following: What kind of “historiography” appertains to the false past set
up by déjà vu? What type of historical narration establishes itself at the “end
of history”?
Nietzsche discerned three possible approaches to the
cadaster of
res gestae. He termed monumental that history (read:
historiography) which strives to present models worthy of emulation: “a
collection of ‘effects in themselves’ of events that will have an effect in
every age.”
13 Critical history
is that concerned with “passing judgment on and destroying the past”: it is
cultivated by those of us who, unable to bear the miserable present, attempt
“to give ourselves
a posteriori, as it were, a new past from which
we would prefer to be descended, as opposed to that past from which we actually
descended.”
14
Finally (though taking the middle place in Nietzsche’s
ordering), there is
antiquarian history, which “preserves and
venerates” the past, as it really was, in its totality, without missing out the
slightest detail.
15 For
the antiquarian historian,
everything deserves to be kept
alive in memory: the village fête, an incidental comment that just slipped out,
the humble “almost vanishing traces” of history. Monumental historiography can
degenerate into overblown rhetoric, and the critical approach into peevish
rancor: however, since each of them maintains a certain link with activity and
the unfolding of history, their overabundance is harmful to life to only a
limited degree. Only the excess of antiquarian history causes irreparable
damage. Its stunning suggestion that we ought to remember every particular raises
the specter of hypermnesia, which Nietzsche discusses right at the beginning of
this text: “Imagine the most extreme example, a human being who does not
possess the power to forget.”
16 This
extreme case, at first brought up as a bogeyman, becomes a
routine when
antiquarian history has its way. It flourishes untroubled even “when history
itself is lost”—even and
especially then.
The pseudo-past, when we are being led on by the déjà vu,
does not allow for filters or choices. Rather, it appears to be “preserving and
venerating” everything, almost as if it were a vivid hic et nunc. Antiquarian
historiography lovingly tends to the “once upon a time” evoked by false
recognition. But, we should repeat, here “historiography” must not be taken to
mean specialist knowledge, but rather a widespread and even banalized
existential attitude. Correlating extremely closely to the post-historical mood,
the antiquarian attitude is an indelible component of the forms of life
characterized by the déjà vu as public pathology. But of what, exactly, does
this attitude consist?
The “past” to be preserved and venerated (and this
veneration’s only requite is in mimesis) is nothing other than the present: or
better, the present smuggled in place of something that already happened,
through a real anachronism. Antiquarian historiography applies its own typical
methods to actuality: everything that happens is treated as suggestive evidence,
while it is still happening; the current moment is consumed by nostalgia.
But the antiquarian inclination ought to have a more specific name for when it
is concentrated on the present: modernariat. In its common usage,
this term designates the—sentimental, aesthetic, commercial—interest in objects
and artifacts belonging to the recent past (so recent, it skirts on today): the
music of the 1960s, the political posters of the following decade, and then,
continuing onward, the washing machine that just gave up the ghost, or last
summer’s fashionable hats. In the radical usage that we here propose,
“modernariat” instead means the systematic development of an antiquarian
sensibility with regard to thehic et nunc being lived at any given
moment. In one sense, the modernariat is a symptom of the doubling of the
present as an illusory “already-been”; but it also actively contributes to the
ever-renewed realization of this double.
The modernariat is the historiographical genre that prevails
when History always seems to be setting the pace; when, that is, it seems—as
Bergson wrote of the déjà vu—“that the
future is closed, that the
situation is detached from everything although I am attached to it.”
17
The antiquarian history of the present gives rise to what
Nietzsche called “a blind mania to collect.”
18 The
modernariat develops a sort of cult of whatever happens to exist
now:
it surveys it with “insatiable curiosity” and attributes it the stunning
fascination and prestige of destiny. Walter Benjamin tried to put some of the
prerogatives of the “antiquarian” approach to the service of “critical”
history, or to make the antiquariat supremely critical: as such, he sang the
praises of the collector (think of his “Edward Fuchs, Collector and Historian”
19)
and his vocation of redeeming the “oppressed past” sabotaged by the victors of
history, with special concern for the lowly, the hidden and the silenced.
Benjamin’s proposal is, today, being hideously caricatured by part of the
modernariat, who favor a particular form of collecting: not to bring out in the
present the plot of a thorny past which has been misunderstood (i.e.,
Benjamin’s intention), but rather to give the present the stigmata of a sacred
and unmodifiable past. Not satisfied with contemplating the “now” as if it were
a “back then,” the post-historical collector also nurtures a certain admiration
for it, to the extent of concluding that “it’s too late to do anything better.”
The antiquarian history of the present, or modernariat, is
wholly at one with the society of the spectacle. In turn, we could
say that the society of the spectacle is the modernariat raised to the nth
degree. The “blind mania to collect” of our time understands the present day as
a sort of world’s fair. An exhibition, that is, where the same individual
attends both as an actor (“playing a role—for most people, many roles, thus
playing them all superficially and badly”) and as a spectator “wandering in
search of pleasure.” That is, they are their own spectators; or rather, though
it is the same thing, they collect their own life while it is
passing, rather than living it. Why is the present incessantly duplicated as
the spectacle of the present? Why does it take on the aspect of a “world’s
fair”?
Such questions have become rhetorical, by now. The present
is duplicated because of the déjà vu. When we feel that we are simultaneously
both acting in and spectating on our lives, this is a case of false
recognition. It is then, according to Bergson, that a person “is looking on at
his own movements, thoughts and actions,” such as to split him into two people,
as if one were “an actor playing a part” for the other, spectating.
20 Far
from only referring to the growing consumption of cultural commodities, the
notion of the spectacle concerns, first and foremost, the post-historical
inclination towards
watching oneself live. To put it another way:
the spectacle is the form that the déjà vu takes, as soon as this becomes an
exterior, public form beyond one’s own person. The society of the spectacle
offers people the “world’s fair” of their own capacity to do, to speak and to be—but
reduced to already-performed actions, already-spoken phrases, and
already-complete events.
1 [A
reference to Luigi Pirandello. –Trans.]
2 Henri
Bergson, “Memory of the Present and False Recognition,” in
Key Writings(London:
Continuum, 2002), 149.
3 Jean
Baudrillard,
The Illusion of the End(Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 1994), 9.
4 Bergson,
“Memory of the Present and False Recognition,” 155.
5 Karl
Mannheim,
Ideology and Utopia(London: Routledge, 1936), 235–36.
6 Bergson,
“The Possible and the Real,” in
Key Writings (London: Continuum,
2002), 230.
7 Bergson,
“Memory of the Present and False Recognition,” 148.
9 The
future perfect verb tense is of some significance in both Bergson’s essay on
the déjà vu and that concerning the possible. In “Le Souvenir du present et la
fausse reconnaissance” (
Revue Philosophique de la France et de I’Etranger [Dec.
1908]: 561), he writes: “As we witness an event or participate in a
conversation, there suddenly arises the conviction that we have already seen
what we are seeing, already heard what we are hearing, and already said what is
being said … in sum, we are reliving down to the last detail an instant of our
own past life. The illusion is sometimes so strong that in each moment, as long
as this illusion lasts, we believe ourselves to be at the point of predicting
what is about to happen: how could we not know already, if we feel that soon
we
will know that we knew it?” [Italics added. This passage does not appear in
the existing English translation in
Key Writings. –Trans.]
10 Augustine,
Confessions,
Book XI, Chapter 20.
11 Alexandre
Kojève,
Introduction to the Reading of Hegel (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1980). In the text I focus exclusively on the long note in
which he develops the discussion from the twelfth of his 1938–39 lectures at
the École pratique des hautes études.
12 Baudrillard,
The
Illusion of the End, 27, 73.
13 The
Nietzsche Reader, eds. Keith Ansell Pearson and Duncan Large (Oxford:
Blackwell, 2006), 133–34.
17 Bergson,
“Memory of the Present and False Recognition,” 155.
18 Nietzsche
Reader, 137.
19 Translation
in
New German Critique 5 (1975): 27–58.
20 Bergson,
“Memory of the Present and False Recognition,” 150.